fax (000) 000-0000
toll-free (000) 000-0000
Carl von Clausewitz believed that a useful theory must include all
elements that pertain to battle. Not just the measurable, such as
physical distances, but also the intangible, such as "morale and the
commanders' psychology," and "common sense and logic." Theory gives
structure to fact, relates the past to the present through logical
links, and strengthens and refines judgment. Or as Clausewitz said,
"An accurate and penetrating understanding is a more useful and
essential asset for the commander than any gift for cunning."
Clausewitz presented his ideas as timeless and consistent theory of
conflict. He sought to discover a universal nature of warfare, while
illustrating his principles through the use of specific examples.
His background and experiences, and the fact that the national state
in Prussia was militarized quickly and performed reasonably well in
war even when they had committed only "part of their military
resources," certainly influenced his ideas. But Clausewitz was
foremost a practical soldier over a theoretician and had spent most
of his life participating in warfare in one way or another. He
believed that those
who have no knowledge other than that derived from experience have
only experience to fall back on, and all action will therefore arise
based on prior experience.
At the heart of his theory is the theme that war is talked about in
one way and exercised in another. War is therefore neither a
complete science, nor a complete art.
Science is the act of knowing, and art is the act of doing. Science
requires knowledge, but art requires judgment.
Since the practice of art requires individual talent, or the
capacity to create, it is not possible to establish a set of rules,
for instance, that hold true in every situation for every commander.
War employs constant change. Crafting a universal strategy for
warfare that proves useful in every situation is therefore not
possible.
Along these lines, Clausewitz also believed that mathematical laws,
and particularly numbers, although used by theoreticians to
calculate probable outcomes and provide definite figures, cannot
stand the test of practical application. Numbers become arbitrary in
the art of war, and tend to force "theorists into a direction
opposed to common sense." The combat itself is the only way to make
sense of war. In this regard, there are three critical operations of
the mind: historical investigation, the determination of doubtful
facts, and the tracing of effects and causes. All things have to be
traced to the beginning, and not rest on arbitrary assumptions and
suppositions.
Rules should therefore be guidelines, or points of reference, to
which the commander applies his judgment, and actions must be
modified upon passing from theory to reality. This is also why war
belongs neither entirely to science nor entirely to art, but rather
to social life since it is a conflict of interests.
Although Clausewitz acknowledged the social component of war, he
ignored ethics in his study, because he considered it not belonging
to the "theory of war." The "social act" of war "lies beyond war
itself."
When morals are mixed with theories, rules dissolve into vague
ideas. The conduct of war and the morality of war must therefore be
separated. The military strategist does not consider whether the
objective is ethical or not. He thinks only of winning the war.
Although Clausewitz recognized the futility of using scientific
calculations in the art of war, his theories of conflict do not
completely discredit scientific warfare, however. A prescriptive set
of rules does bring familiarity to the commander and soldiers and
can, at least to an extent, be applied to discipline and battlefield
formations. When a soldier knows his position in the formation, the
risk of encountering uncertainty and chance is reduced. Furthermore,
although the enemy's will is difficult to control and the element of
chance can strike either belligerent, in order to create a set of
workable guidelines for war, one must conduct a "comprehensive and
scientific analysis."
While others categorized wars into different sets of philosophies;
for example, the eschatological philosophy, which states that there
will be a final war, normally of divine influence, after which there
will be no more wars (as when Christ returns), Clausewitz believed
that wars were purely political in nature.
Prior to the Age of Enlightenment and the French Revolution, war was
mainly the concern of the government and not of the people. Since
the government was viewed as a separate entity from the state (which
was, in fact, the people), the government could not recruit a truly
efficient army, but must rely on recruiting the poorer people who
were willing to serve, or on mercenaries who lacked a sense of
patriotism and could become a threat to those in power if not paid
well. There were other drawbacks. For example, when the state could
not recruit quality personnel, and had to rely only on the money in
its coffers and could thus gauge the enemy's potential, war was
"deprived of its most dangerous feature—its tendency toward the
extreme, and of the whole chain of unknown possibilities that would
follow."
In Clausewitz's time, by contrast, the capacity to wage war had
evolved to a point where a state's military power depended on its
financial capacity, and its capacity to enlist the masses in
military service. The responsibility for war fell on the government,
to which the people were obligated to serve and pay taxes. The power
of the government thus grew stronger than in the past.
The basic tenets of Clausewitz's philosophy of international
relations hold that the state is a living, sovereign entity with the
goal to increase its power at the expense of other states. States
are therefore always in conflict with one another, and war consists
of one state imposing its will on another. Since nations and empires
are built through violence and continue to relate to each other
through violence, warfare cannot be avoided, at least not for an
extended period of time, and should therefore be accepted as a
normal state of human existence.
Clausewitz definition of war is that "war is an act of violence to
compel our opponent to fulfill our will." If
it were not for certain frictions and physical limitations, war
would always be absolute, where every action would be directed
toward the achievement of victory. A head of state, who dared not
justify starting a war by imposing his will on the opponent, or who
would fight a purely defensive war, was, in Clausewitz's view, "an
absurdity."
War should thus not be waged for its own sake, but should be a rational effort and lead to the achievement of some gain or higher political objective. War should also be waged with the aim of achieving victory as quickly as possible. In accordance with these thoughts, war should not be waged for personal glory or a desire for adventure. War should be fought by the state only for the purpose of achieving a defined political objective, and never for adventurist reasons. Since quick victory was of primary concern, World War I, for example, which was waged over a period of years in a seemingly stalemate condition, would be a poor example of Clausewitz's philosophy of what war is and should be.